I ended my last
post with the comment:
..the
validity of the logic depends on the truth of the premise. I’m afraid the world
is bordering on insanity on this issue, and is willing to deny the truth in
order to pursue the logic of the culture of death.
I actually wrote those words last September. A few days ago,
I discovered that the world was teetering over the edge of that insanity border
when I read the
LifeSiteNews story that came out on February 28, 2012, entitled “Ethicists
Justify Infanticide in Major Medical Journal”.
We are surely plummeting down that slippery slope now. LSN
reported that:
Taking the logic of abortion to
its ultimate consequence, two ethicists have argued that “killing a newborn
could be ethically permissible in all the circumstances where abortion would
be.”
[The writers] have made the
case that since both the unborn baby and the newborn do not have the moral
status of actual persons and are consequently morally irrelevant, what
they call “after-birth abortion” should be permissible in all the cases where
abortion is, including cases where the newborn is perfectly healthy.
There are no words to describe how sick and perverted that
reasoning is. But it is the logical
consequence of both the abortive and contraceptive mind sets that prevail in
this country.
All these ethicists are doing is coming up with twisted
reasoning and re-definition of terms in order to justify the killing of
newborns. They are blunt in the words they use, but intellectually dishonest in
their re-definition of terms. Have you read the actual paper? It is available here.
Here’s an example of their convoluted reasoning (all
emphases mine):
In spite of the oxymoron in the
expression, we propose to call this practice
‘after-birth abortion’, rather than ‘infanticide’, to emphasize that the moral status of the individual killed
is comparable with that of a fetus
(on which ‘abortions’ in the traditional sense are performed) rather than to
that of a child. Therefore, we claim
that killing a newborn could be
ethically permissible in all the circumstances where abortion would be. Such
circumstances include cases where
the newborn has the potential to have an (at least) acceptable life, but the well-being of the family is at risk.
Accordingly, a second terminological
specification is that we call such a practice ‘after-birth abortion’ rather than ‘euthanasia’ because the best interest of the one who dies is not necessarily the primary criterion
for the choice, contrary to what happens in the case of euthanasia.
At least the authors of that paper are honest enough to
admit that they are talking about “killing newborns” – a phrase they use a
number of times. And they are chillingly
and brutally honest about the fact that they believe that “what’s best for the child”
is not at all of concern. They dodge the entire issue of whether a baby with
a disability or disease would be able to live a “meaningful” or “acceptable”
life simply by acknowledging that “it is hard to find definitive arguments to
the effect that life with certain pathologies is not worth living”, and then
focusing on the needs of others, whose
rights take precedence over the rights of the person to be killed:
Nonetheless,
to bring up such children might be an unbearable burden on the family
and on society as a whole, when the state economically provides for their care.
On these grounds, the fact that a fetus has the potential to become a person
who will have an (at least) acceptable life is no reason for prohibiting
abortion. Therefore, we argue that, when circumstances occur after birth such
that they would have justified abortion, what we call after-birth
abortion should be permissible.
Gee, if only their parents had had the option...NOT. |
In other words, because it is
permissible to abort an unborn baby who is prenatally diagnosed with a
debilitating disorder or disease, it’s also permissible and morally neutral to
kill the newborn who was not diagnosed
prenatally, but showed up with debilitating symptoms at birth. It’s not about
whether “life is worth living” for the baby; it’s about whether life is worth living
(for the family) with the
baby.
Not only this, but the authors add
other situations that justify killing a newborn:
…or
if economical, social or psychological circumstances change such that
taking care of the offspring becomes an unbearable burden on someone,
then people should be given the chance of not being forced to do something
they cannot afford.
So…if the parent(s) simply change
their minds about “wanting” the child, it should be permissible for them to kill
the baby. This is simply exalting the self above another human being. It is
diabolical.
The authors also attempt to
forestall any “personhood” arguments. They deny the “actual” personhood of the
unborn and the newborn child, but placate us with an acknowledgement that these
little ones are “potential persons”:
Although
fetuses and newborns are not persons, they are potential persons because
they can develop, thanks to their own biological mechanisms, those properties
which will make them ‘persons’ in the sense of ‘subjects of a moral right to
life’: that is, the point at which they will be able to make aims and appreciate
their own life.
Yet, they claim that it does not make sense to claim
that a fetus or newborn is “harmed” by being denied the chance to develop into
an “actual” person:
However,
whereas you can benefit someone by bringing her into existence (if her life is
worth living), it makes no sense to say that someone is harmed by being
prevented from becoming an actual person. The reason is that, by virtue of
our definition of the concept of ‘harm’ in the previous section, in order for
a harm to occur, it is necessary that someone is in the condition of
experiencing that harm.
If a
potential person, like a fetus and a newborn, does not become an actual person,
like you and us, then there is neither an actual nor a future person who can
be harmed, which means that there is no harm at all. So, if you ask
one of us if we would have been harmed, had our parents decided to kill us when
we were fetuses or newborns, our answer is ‘no’, because they would have
harmed someone who does not exist (the ‘us’ whom you are asking the question),
which means no one. And if no one is harmed, then no harm occurred.
Sort of like the age old question: if a tree falls
in the forest, and no one is there to witness it...Oh dear. If you buy this, I
have some ocean-view property in Arizona I would like to sell you. This is
double-speak, pure and simple. It is false logic because it is based on the
false premise that the fetus or newborn is not an “actual” person.
What about adoption? Surely these ethicists might
agree that since the baby is actually born,
adoption would surely be the preferred option if the parents truly do not want
their child. No…they again cater to their perception of the needs of the
mother, completely denying the right to life of the child.
…[W]e
also need to consider the interests of the mother who might suffer psychological
distress from giving her child up for adoption. Birthmothers are often
reported to experience serious psychological problems due to the inability to
elaborate their loss and to cope with their grief. It is true that grief
and sense of loss may accompany both abortion and after-birth abortion as well as
adoption, but we cannot assume that for the birthmother the latter is
the least traumatic. For example, ‘those who grieve a death must accept the
irreversibility of the loss, but natural mothers often dream that their child
will return to them. This makes it difficult to accept the reality of
the loss because they can never be quite sure whether or not it is irreversible’.
Wow. I do believe these ethicists have forgotten to
do their homework on the psychological effects of abortion on women. As we
know, those effects are profound and long-lasting, even when the abortion was
performed on a “clump of cells” and the mother had not even seen her baby.
Imagine the devastating psychological and emotional after-effects of giving
birth to a baby and then authorizing
the child’s death!
But, then, it’s all about the actual people, not the potential
people, according to these ethicists:
…[T]the
rights and interests of the actual people involved should represent
the prevailing consideration in a decision about abortion and
after-birth abortion.
And just exactly when
does the “potential” person become an “actual” person? The authors don’t really
know. But they know you can’t wait too
long:
…[W]e
do not put forward any claim about the moment at which after-birth abortion
would no longer be permissible, and we do not think that in fact more than a
few days would be necessary for doctors to detect any abnormality in the
child. In cases where the after-birth abortion were requested for nonmedical
reasons, we do not suggest any threshold, as it depends on the
neurological development of newborns, which is something neurologists and
psychologists would be able to assess.
So these “ethicists” have opened
the Pandora’s box of the killing of human beings whom others have decided are a
“burden”, and they have left the window of time for such killings to occur up to
other “experts”. We are on the slippery
slope, we are much closer to the abyss, and the grade is getting steeper.
I suggested in my earlier post that
the difference between the killing of an unborn baby by an abortionist versus
the killing of a newborn baby by the mother is only a separation of a small
slice of time and the difference of physical location. Now these “ethicists”
have made that difference even smaller.
It is a small step from here to
killing other defenseless individuals who are deemed to be a “burden” on their
families – those with profound disabilities, extreme retardation, lack of
cognitive ability…coma…persistent “vegetative” state…elderly…etc. Do you see where this is going? When the family gets
tired of dealing with the “burden” – who we can re-classify as not an “actual” person because of a lack
of awareness, or for whatever reasons we want – then the person can be killed.
And just a little farther down the
slope will come the declaration that, even if the family does not consider the individual a burden, society might – especially if social and
medical services are being provided at a cost to the state (as in…hmm…Obamacare).
Here’s one more telling paragraph
from the article:
…[A]s
we have just argued, merely potential people cannot be harmed by not being
brought into existence. Actual people’s well-being could be threatened by
the new (even if healthy) child requiring energy, money and care which
the family might happen to be in short supply of. …[S]ince non-persons
have no moral rights to life, there are no reasons for banning
after-birth abortions. We might still have moral duties towards future
generations in spite of these future people not existing yet…This argument,
however, does not apply to this particular newborn or infant, because we
are not justified in taking it for granted that she will exist as a
person in the future. Whether she will exist is exactly what our choice is
about.
That last sentence bears repeating:
Whether
she will exist is exactly what our choice is about.
If that is not “playing God”, I don’t know what is.
The caucasians are more prone to abort, for the blacks, the newborns are an income source and for the hispanics, a mixed bag, but mostly Catholics, they thing thrice before aborting. The white are commiting suicide.
ReplyDelete